Stuart
Hameroff, et.al.; Science of Consciousness II |
|
|
|
|
Book |
Page |
|
Topic |
|
|
|
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
40 Hz oscillations in the cerebral cortex (Crick and Koch 1990) |
|
|
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Intralamina nucleus in the thalamus (Bogen 1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Reentrant loops in the thalamocortical system (Llinas 1994) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Nucleus reticularis (Taylor and
Alavi 1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Extended reticular-thalamic
activation system (Newman and Baars 1993) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Anterior cingulate system (Cotterill 1994) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Neural assemblies bound by NMDA
(Flohr 1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Temporally extended neural activity (Libert 1994) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Back projections to lower cortical areas (Cauller and Kulics 1991) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
219 |
|
Visual processing within the ventral stream (Milner and Goodale 1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Neurons in visual
cortex projecting to prefrontal areas (Crick and Koch 1995) |
|
1 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Neural activity in V5 (Tootell
1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Certain neurons in the superior temporal sulcus and inferior temporal cortex (Logothetis and
Schall 1989; Sheinberg and Logothetis 1997) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Neuronal gesalts in an epicenter (Greenfield 1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Outputs of a comparator
system in the hippocampus (Gray 1995) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Quantum coherence in microtubules
(Hameroff 1994) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Global workspace (Baars 1988) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
High-quality representations
(Farah 1994) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
Selector inputs to action
systems (Shallice 1988) |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
220 |
|
A number of theories of the neural correlate of consciousness give a major role to interactions between the thalamus and the cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
224 |
|
Working memory
is a major mechanism whereby information is made
available for global
control. |
|
4 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
226 |
|
Crick and Koch have suggested
that the visual NCC is not to be found within V1 because V1 does not contain neurons that project to the prefrontal
cortex. |
|
2 |
|
Chalmers;
Neural Correlate of Consciousness |
227 |
|
If a thalamocortical system turns out to be
the neural correlate of consciousness. |
|
1 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
231 |
|
When does a baby become conscious? |
|
4 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
231 |
|
Consciousness
might dawn sometime in infancy. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
232 |
|
A plausible explanation is that
consciousness has already been long underway in the womb, but if so, when did
the baby become conscious? |
|
1 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
232 |
|
Human brain
has almost the maximal number of neurons by the time the fetus reaches full term. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
232 |
|
In the adult
brain, connections between neurons
infiltrate, penetrate, and iterate thousands and tens of thousands of times between one
cell and the next. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
232 |
|
During early
life the growth and density of neurons is
conspicuous, while the environment crafts individual patterns of connectivity. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
232 |
|
Brain has no fixed consciousness center; we have to imagine that consciousness arises from an assembly
of neurons
that are not preordained but are just transiently large enough. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
232 |
|
It is a paradox in terms to be conscious of nothing; we must always be conscious of something. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
233 |
|
Consciousness
entails some sort of focus
or epicenter. |
|
1 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
233 |
|
In human beings, the sensation of a prick on the skin can
be recorded very quickly on
the appropriate receiving
cortex of the brain. Only after about half a second, however, after the electrical signals have spread over a much larger area, will subjects report that they are conscious of the tingle of the prick. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
233 |
|
Transient
neuronal assemblies are a reality. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
233 |
|
Certain modulator
neurotransmitters
will modify the ease with which neurons are corralled
into joining a group activated
by the pulling
power of the epicenter. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
233 |
|
Size of a transient neuronal assembly will depend upon the strength of the stimulus epicenter. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Mood-modifying drugs such as Prozac
and Ecstasy. |
|
1 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Effect of a chemical depends on its modulating power to determine the size of transient
neuronal assemblies. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Degree of consciousness can be seen as related to the number of neurons recruited in a transient assembly. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Several factors, such as arousal
levels, extent of epicenter associations, and stimulus strength are each
necessary for consciousness, but sufficient only when present together in a
specific way. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Where might these fluctuating neuronal assemblies occur in the brain?
[Gestalts] |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Any one neuron could participate in many networks simultaneously; each neuron has thousands of connections with other neurons,
any of which can be activated under the right conditions. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
For most people most of the
time, we have only one consciousness at any one time. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Consciousness
is spatially multiple but temporally unitary. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
234 |
|
Properties of consciousness could be described
as: (1)
spatially multiple yet effectively unitary at any one time, (2) an emergent property of nonspecialized and divergent groups of neurons that is continuously variable with respect to,
and always entailing, a stimulus epicenter, (3) recruiting power of the epicenter depends on the strength of stimulus signal and extent of associative neuronal conductivity. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
One factor governing neural assembly size, the extent of neuronal connectivity, is forged in later life through neural
network associations accumulated in a lifetime of experience. |
|
1 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
Fetuses at 26 weeks will
exhibit in their brain for the first time consistent electrical activity
indicative of a functioning conscious brain. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
Adult humans
display the REM sleep state a few times
each night, whereas a fetus generates it constantly. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
Fetuses with
their potential for only small
neuronal assemblies have a
dreamlike consciousness;
whereas in adults, small neuronal assemblies will underlie our dreaming consciousness. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
When we are asleep we are far less sensitive to the outside world, hence at this
time we would expect to have smaller neuronal
assemblies due to the lesser
strength of potential
epicenters not activated in the normal way by our sense organs. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
Dreams are a
different experience from normal daytime awareness, with their a ruptures in logic and sudden shifts in scene. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
235 |
|
Psychiatrist and sleep expert Allan Hobson has found that dreaming has certain
parallels to the state of mind of the schizophrenic; the only difference is
that the schizophrenic is in a dream, or perhaps a nightmare, much more of the time. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
236 |
|
Schizophrenia is alleviated by
giving a drug that blocks availability of one modulating chemical that might
be in functional excess. |
|
1 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
236 |
|
In this way it is possible at
the phenomenonological level, to link three very different
conditions -- dreaming, schizophrenia, and childhood -- with a common type of
consciousness. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
236 |
|
Schizophrenic consciousness as a dreamlike
state would be disconnected and highly labile, as assembly after flimsy neuronal assembly, formed and reformed randomly and capriciously. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
236 |
|
Throughout the day, and indeed the night, the depth our consciousness will be constantly changing. |
|
0 |
|
Greenfield;
Rosetta Stone for Mind and Brain |
236 |
|
Noninvasive brain imaging, though the temporal or spatial
resolution
is currently too low
to be appropriate, in a few years
will presumably be sensitive enough that transient populations of neuronal assemblies can be monitored
informatively. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
269 |
|
Theatrical metaphor -- Consciousness corresponds to the bright spot on the stage, and unconscious systems operate "in the dark" backstage and in
the audience. |
|
33 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
269 |
|
Active bright spot on stage corresponds to working memory. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
269 |
|
Contextual systems that reside "backstage," shaping the content of
consciousness without themselves entering consciousness. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
269 |
|
Only the global
workspace (GW) is conscious at any
given moment.
[Edelman's dynamic core] |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Active bright spot may be closely associated with sensory projection areas that provide the detailed content of
sensory consciousness, closely supported by subcortical
systems in
the thalamus, basal ganglia, hippocampus, and brainstem. [Edelman's dynamic core] |
|
1 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Attentional system selects which of several potential inputs will become conscious at any one time. [Edelman's dynamic core] |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Reticular nucleus in the thalamus (nRt), with its ability to gate traffic from sensory surfaces to
cortex, is one natural candidate for a selective attention mechanism. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Several other brain loci for visual attention, notably the anterior cingulate, which may be
associated with effortal attention. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Contextual systems that are subconscious but still shape conscious content may be found in the dorsal visual
pathway,
including right
parietal cortex,
which provides the object-centered framework for visual perception. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Specialized sources of knowledge
that receive conscious input include frontal
cortex, memory related
systems such as the hippocampus, brain mechanisms for automatic routines such as the basal ganglia, and mediating emotional processes such as the limbic system and amygdala. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Brain's gross anatomy shows massive fiber tracts leading from posterior to anterior
cortex,
from one hemisphere to the other, and from cortex to thalamus and back again. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Each of the massive
fiber tracts is known to map
significant features of
conscious information from one location to another. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Broadcasting
of cortical sensory information may occur in several directions from sensory cortex: from back to front, from side to side, and from cortex to midbrain and back again. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
It has been hypothesized that
the neural substrate of the global workspace was an "extended reticular
thalamus activating system," (ERTAS). |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
The "extended
reticular thalamus activating system," (ERTAS) acronym emphasizes that it is centered on the thalamus with its rich, reciprocal projections with the cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
270 |
|
Layer 1 of the
cortex, often viewed as a "feltwork" of neurons that permit not just axonal transmission but horizontal spread of activation. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Cortical sensory
projection areas seem like
a more plausible loci for conscious global workspace, at least for sensory consciousness. |
|
1 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Conscious experience involves ceaseless interaction between input
(from outside and within the brain) and memory. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Conscious experience is relational
-- the conscious content of
a mental experience is
determined by the evocation
and intermingling of
suitable past memories evoked by the input giving rise to
that conscious experience. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Relational feature of conscious experience implies a ceaseless dialogue between conscious content and unconscious systems, notably the hippocampus, basal
ganglia,
and unconscious regions of cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Intermingling of past and
present requires both long-range intermodal and short range intramodal
competition |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Intermodal (global) inhibition via
the nucleus reticularis thalami (nRt). |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt) seems like an ideal device for achieving global input competition, being composed solely
of inhibitory cells and also having remarkable lateral connectivity similar to that of the outer plexiform layer in the retina. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt) may bind activities across modalities. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
Nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt) supports a far more complex form of spatial competition than a simple
winner-take-all form, because it produces a wave over the whole thalamocortical system. There will be many spatial regions over the cortex
that have nonzero activity. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
271 |
|
The centerpiece of the "comparator system" is the hippocampus, but it's activities
are also closely tied to
those of the basal ganglia
and cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Fornix also projects to areas in the basal ganglia, which project to the nucleus reticularis thalami (nRt). |
|
1 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt) possible role in selective attention and conscious processing was pointed out by Crick (1984). |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Because the output
of the nucleus reticularis thalami (nRt) neurons is
itself inhibitory, it's activation disinhibits the sensory relay pathways; i.e. increases entry to the cerebral
cortex by stimuli that are
currently engaging the thalamocortical loops. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
The crucial aspect for consciousness arising from unconscious neural activity is creation of relatively lasting "bubbles" of activity in cortex by local recurrence. It is proposed that such activity
singles out cortical regions with highest density of cells in layers 2 and 3. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Neural underpinnings of the global workspace by means of the excellent intercortical
connectivity of such regions as parietal, inferotemporal and frontal
cortices. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Detailed coding of the content of consciousness appears to be cortical, however, much of the thalamus is involved. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
At any one time, different sensory inputs, including such
"inner" inputs as visual imagery and inner speech, compete for access
to consciousness. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Other possible
inputs to consciousness
include abstract conscious
content such as beliefs and
ideas. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Materials selected to be conscious involves both top-down influences and bottom-up inputs. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Top-down influences include goal systems associated with frontal cortex, emotional and motivation
systems
combining limbic and
right frontal cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Conscious content reflects an endless interplay of competition and cooperation between possible inputs and top-down influences. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
A totally inhibitory system that greatly contributes to global
competition is the basal
ganglia. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
272 |
|
Neural model of frontal lobe executive function |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Brainstem-thalamocortical axis supports
the state, but not the detailed content of consciousness, which is produced by cortex. |
|
1 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Anatomy and putative functions
of the "neural global workspace," extending from the midbrain reticular
formation to prefrontal
cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
"Global attentional
matrix" centered on the nucleus
reticularis thalami (nRt), which both gates information flow to and from the cortex and regulates electrical oscillatory patterns throughout the cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Resource allocation as "global attention" -- it's core neural mechanism is an array of gating circuits in the nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt), which covers the lateral surfaces of the thalamus. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Through the nucleus
reticularis thalami (nRt) pass nearly all of the
pathways coursing between the thalamus and the cerebral hemispheres. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Via the reciprocal, nucleus reticularis thalami (nRt) circuits, the cerebral
cortex and brainstem
reticular formation selectively modulate their own information processing activities in serving conscious perceptions, intentions or plans or both. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
A selective
attention system, including the nucleus reticularis thalami (nRt), selects among multiple
possible conscious contents. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Attentional selection of conscious content appears to operate by means of the nucleus
reticularis thalami (nRt), influenced by several
centers from brain stem to
the prefrontal cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt) is believed to gate the sensory thalamus nuclei, which flow up to the primary projection areas in the cortex,
and is the most strategic position for controlling sensory input. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Almost 10
times as many visual neurons go down from the visual cortex to the thalamus as the other way, suggesting continuous
and intimate looping between thalamus and
cortex,
controlled by nucleus reticularis thalami
(nRt). |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
A voluntary
component may also act via the anterior cingulate gyrus and the vigilance network of prefrontal cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Attentional selection is also influenced
by the content of consciousness, suggesting that reentrant loops from sensory cortex descend to the major
sensory nuclei of the thalamus to create a self-sustaining feedback loop, again under nucleus reticularis
thalami (nRt) control. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Posterior
cortex provides sensory conscious content whereas anterior cortex is involved in active voluntary control. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
273 |
|
Consciousness
containing phenomenal experience. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
274 |
|
Frontal motor cortical systems such as those involved in thinking and
reasoning. |
|
1 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
274 |
|
Memoral structures needed to give content to consciousness -- primary sensory, postprimary, associative, and heteromodal
cortices, all of which are posterior. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
274 |
|
Active consciousness -- involved
in thinking and planning as well as responding in a willful manner. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
274 |
|
Active consciousness has its major activity involved with anterior
cortical, related thalamic, and basal ganglia neural sites, which are known to be crucially involved with actions of either direct motor action or of thought, planning. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
275 |
|
Remarkable innerconnectivity among all parts of the brain. Iin the visual system we find top-down feedback from higher visual areas to lower areas, as well as a bottom-up flow going the other way. |
|
1 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
275 |
|
In thalamocortical
loops, the downflowing
neurons outnumber the upgoing ones by a ratio of almost ten to one. |
|
0 |
|
Baars; Neuronal Mechanisms of Consciousness |
275 |
|
Blindsight
analogues in auditory and somatosensory cortex. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
279 |
|
Consciousness
becomes a problem only at a point at which subjective experience occurs. |
|
4 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
279 |
|
No problem understanding
in principle how brain can carry out the processing of information that is
required to link input from the environment through to subsequent behavior. [Bayesian
inference] [Fuster's perception-action cycle] |
|
0 |
|
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
279 |
|
Hard problem
is that we have no understanding of how the sequence
of brain activities give rise to conscious experience. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
280 |
|
Hard problems
of consciousness cover the perceived
world with all of its qualities (visual, auditory, olfactory, etc.), as well as bodily sensations, proprioception, emotional feelings, dreams, hallucinations,
mental images, and internal
speech. |
|
1 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
280 |
|
Integrate into the rest of
science the qualitative aspects of
our perceptions of the external world (e.g., the color red, the smell of a rose, the feel of
cold water on the tongue, the feel of velvet
on the skin),
the more internal aspects of conscious experience (mental images, internally spoken or imaged thoughts, dreams, etc.). |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
280 |
|
Many distinguish scientists and
philosophers do not accept a hard problem of consciousness, stated in this or
any other way (e.g., Dennet 1991). |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
281 |
|
Four key questions of a successful theory of consciousness. |
|
1 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
281 |
|
(1) How did conscious
experiences evolved? |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
281 |
|
(2) How do conscious experiences
confer survival value? |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
281 |
|
(3) How do conscious experiences
arise out of brain events? |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
281 |
|
(4) How do conscious experiences
alter behavior with which they are associated? |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
281 |
|
Consciousness comes too late to affect the processes to which it is apparently linked. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
283 |
|
Famous Turing
Test, by answering questions indistinguishably from
the answers given by human being. |
|
2 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
283 |
|
It is all in the physics, a view
recently advocated by Hameroff and Penrose (1996) |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
284 |
|
Bizarre aberrations of conscious
experience that characterize acute schizophrenia. |
|
1 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
284 |
|
Comparator hypothesis has the general function of predicting, moment by moment, (where
a moment is about a 10th of a second long), the next
perceived state of the world, comparing this state
to the next perceived state, and determining whether
the predicted and actual states do in fact match. [recursion] [Bayesian inference]
[Fuster's perception-action
cycle] |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
284 |
|
Subicular region of the hippocampal formation is where the key comparisons are postulated to take place. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
284 |
|
Consciousness
consists of activity in the subbicular comparator, together with feedback from the
comparator to the sets of
neurons and perceptual systems that have provided inputs to the comparator for current
comparison. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
284 |
|
Consciousness comes too late to
affect on-line behavior. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Features of the contents of
consciousness for which the comparator hypothesis offers an account. (table) |
|
1 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Consciousness experience is closely linked to current action plans. [Fuster's perception-action cycle] |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
We are conscious of the outputs
of motor programs, not of the program itself. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Consciousness occurs too late to
affect outcomes of the processes to which they are apparently linked. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Conscious events occur on a time scale about two orders of magnitude slower than the neural events that underlie
them. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Conscious experience has a spatiotemporal unity quite unlike the patterns of neuronal events that underlie it. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Conscious experience consists of a series of constructions based on a model of the world, not direct reflections of inputs from the world. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Consciousness is highly
selective. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Neuronal events operate in
parallel; consciousness operates serially. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
285 |
|
Conscious experience is closely linked to memory. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
288 |
|
Sensory systems are modular. |
|
3 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
288 |
|
Synesthesia is
a mixing of the senses. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
288 |
|
Normal selective neuronal cell
death during infancy. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
288 |
|
In the normally
developing brain in many species, many more neuronal connections are made
than are finally retained; redundant or maladaptive
connections being "pruned"
during infancy. |
|
0 |
|
Gray; Hard Question of Consciousness |
288 |
|
In synesthesia, the suggestion has been made that the redundant
connections may persist. Perhaps synesthesia has its origins in infancy. |
|
0 |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|